登陆注册
5290600000005

第5章 2(3)

There are few facts of the 'necessary' type that can form the basis of rhetorical syllogisms. Most of the things about which we make decisions, and into which therefore we inquire, present us with alternative possibilities. For it is about our actions that we deliberate and inquire, and all our actions have a contingent character; hardly any of them are determined by necessity. Again, conclusions that state what is merely usual or possible must be drawn from premisses that do the same, just as 'necessary' conclusions must be drawn from 'necessary' premisses; this too is clear to us from the Analytics. It is evident, therefore, that the propositions forming the basis of enthymemes, though some of them may be 'necessary', will most of them be only usually true. Now the materials of enthymemes are Probabilities and Signs, which we can see must correspond respectively with the propositions that are generally and those that are necessarily true. A Probability is a thing that usually happens; not, however, as some definitions would suggest, anything whatever that usually happens, but only if it belongs to the class of the 'contingent' or 'variable'. It bears the same relation to that in respect of which it is probable as the universal bears to the particular. Of Signs, one kind bears the same relation to the statement it supports as the particular bears to the universal, the other the same as the universal bears to the particular. The infallible kind is a 'complete proof' (tekmerhiou); the fallible kind has no specific name. By infallible signs I mean those on which syllogisms proper may be based: and this shows us why this kind of Sign is called 'complete proof': when people think that what they have said cannot be refuted, they then think that they are bringing forward a 'complete proof', meaning that the matter has now been demonstrated and completed (peperhasmeuou); for the word 'perhas' has the same meaning (of 'end' or 'boundary') as the word 'tekmarh' in the ancient tongue. Now the one kind of Sign (that which bears to the proposition it supports the relation of particular to universal) may be illustrated thus. Suppose it were said, 'The fact that Socrates was wise and just is a sign that the wise are just'. Here we certainly have a Sign; but even though the proposition be true, the argument is refutable, since it does not form a syllogism. Suppose, on the other hand, it were said, 'The fact that he has a fever is a sign that he is ill', or, 'The fact that she is giving milk is a sign that she has lately borne a child'. Here we have the infallible kind of Sign, the only kind that constitutes a complete proof, since it is the only kind that, if the particular statement is true, is irrefutable.

The other kind of Sign, that which bears to the proposition it supports the relation of universal to particular, might be illustrated by saying, 'The fact that he breathes fast is a sign that he has a fever'. This argument also is refutable, even if the statement about the fast breathing be true, since a man may breathe hard without having a fever.

It has, then, been stated above what is the nature of a Probability, of a Sign, and of a complete proof, and what are the differences between them. In the Analytics a more explicit description has been given of these points; it is there shown why some of these reasonings can be put into syllogisms and some cannot.

The 'example' has already been described as one kind of induction; and the special nature of the subject-matter that distinguishes it from the other kinds has also been stated above. Its relation to the proposition it supports is not that of part to whole, nor whole to part, nor whole to whole, but of part to part, or like to like. When two statements are of the same order, but one is more familiar than the other, the former is an 'example'. The argument may, for instance, be that Dionysius, in asking as he does for a bodyguard, is scheming to make himself a despot. For in the past Peisistratus kept asking for a bodyguard in order to carry out such a scheme, and did make himself a despot as soon as he got it; and so did Theagenes at Megara; and in the same way all other instances known to the speaker are made into examples, in order to show what is not yet known, that Dionysius has the same purpose in making the same request: all these being instances of the one general principle, that a man who asks for a bodyguard is scheming to make himself a despot. We have now described the sources of those means of persuasion which are popularly supposed to be demonstrative.

There is an important distinction between two sorts of enthymemes that has been wholly overlooked by almost everybody-one that also subsists between the syllogisms treated of in dialectic. One sort of enthymeme really belongs to rhetoric, as one sort of syllogism really belongs to dialectic; but the other sort really belongs to other arts and faculties, whether to those we already exercise or to those we have not yet acquired. Missing this distinction, people fail to notice that the more correctly they handle their particular subject the further they are getting away from pure rhetoric or dialectic. This statement will be clearer if expressed more fully. I mean that the proper subjects of dialectical and rhetorical syllogisms are the things with which we say the regular or universal Lines of Argument are concerned, that is to say those lines of argument that apply equally to questions of right conduct, natural science, politics, and many other things that have nothing to do with one another. Take, for instance, the line of argument concerned with 'the more or less'. On this line of argument it is equally easy to base a syllogism or enthymeme about any of what nevertheless are essentially disconnected subjects-right conduct, natural science, or anything else whatever. But there are also those special Lines of Argument which are based on such propositions as apply only to particular groups or classes of things. Thus there are propositions about natural science on which it is impossible to base any enthymeme or syllogism about ethics, and other propositions about ethics on which nothing can be based about natural science. The same principle applies throughout. The general Lines of Argument have no special subject-matter, and therefore will not increase our understanding of any particular class of things. On the other hand, the better the selection one makes of propositions suitable for special Lines of Argument, the nearer one comes, unconsciously, to setting up a science that is distinct from dialectic and rhetoric. One may succeed in stating the required principles, but one's science will be no longer dialectic or rhetoric, but the science to which the principles thus discovered belong. Most enthymemes are in fact based upon these particular or special Lines of Argument; comparatively few on the common or general kind. As in the therefore, so in this work, we must distinguish, in dealing with enthymemes, the special and the general Lines of Argument on which they are to be founded. By special Lines of Argument I mean the propositions peculiar to each several class of things, by general those common to all classes alike.

We may begin with the special Lines of Argument. But, first of all, let us classify rhetoric into its varieties. Having distinguished these we may deal with them one by one, and try to discover the elements of which each is composed, and the propositions each must employ.

同类推荐
热门推荐
  • 新杨家将

    新杨家将

    五代时期,战火纷飞,后周皇帝柴荣一死,赵匡胤黄袍加身,建立大宋。赵匡胤建国之后,立即着手,统一,然而在他生前依旧有两大遗憾,一是北汉仍旧是割据政权,二是牛原屏障燕云十六州仍在。契丹的掌控之中。赵光义当皇帝后,费了九牛二虎之力拿下北汉,招降了北汉的著名将领杨业……
  • 蒋廷黻回忆录·增补版

    蒋廷黻回忆录·增补版

    蒋廷黻作为一个有着特殊经历和身份的“重要人物”,其回忆录有着较为重要的史料参考价值。本书系作者退休后在哥伦比亚大学口述自传的中文译本,1979年由台湾传记文学出版社出版,曾引起海内外学界广泛关注。蒋廷黻一生经历复杂,亲历了时代的风云变幻。他以学者的眼光与头脑进行观察思考,有人所未道之处。加之长期身处高位,回忆录中披露的大量鲜为人知的史事,更是研究近现代历史的珍贵资料。这是该书的主要价值所在,也是我们出版该书的着眼点。
  • 诗人哲学家:叔本华

    诗人哲学家:叔本华

    古往今来,有多少中外名人不断地涌现在人们的目光里,这些出类拔萃、彪炳千古、流芳百世的名人中,有家国天下的政治家,有叱咤风云的军事家,有超乎凡人的思想家,有妙笔生花的文学家,有造福人类的科学家,有想象非凡的艺术家……他们永远不会被人们忘记!本书遴选了人类历史上最富影响力、最具个性的名人——叔本华,作者结合青少年的阅读习惯,用生动活泼、严谨细腻的笔触向读者介绍了这些世界知名人士的生平故事、理想追求和光辉业绩,为广大读者描绘了一幅幅极具传奇色彩而又引人入胜的名人人生画卷,是青少年学生最佳的成长伴侣。
  • 清代学术概论

    清代学术概论

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。汇聚授权电子版权。
  • 快穿之她又被杀了

    快穿之她又被杀了

    因为想实现一个愿望,苏寂成为一块石头的任务者;为了完成任务,她不得不去守护一群对她心怀不轨的主角......简单点:这是一个有病的妹子在各个世界里虐恋情深的故事。无男主,故事里的主角有男有女。女主没有心(是真的没有),为了达到目的可以牺牲自己的一切。
  • 逃路拐妻进行时:超级吃货

    逃路拐妻进行时:超级吃货

    她是表面高冷内心逗比的吃货神子,他是身份另有乾坤的智障大少爷。然,本应毫无关系的两人,因为一不小心,被死死拴在一起。初遇,“墨璃潇!隔壁小胖欺负我!你帮我揍回去好不好?”“不好。”“秋老爷子的叫花鸡你吃不吃?”“好。”第二天,隔壁小胖变成了一坨不明物体,只有一口气吊着。熟识,“璃潇!我同学家出现了一只妖怪!弄死它好不好?”“……不好。”“庄大小姐的甜品翻新了,你吃不?”“好。”第二天,某妖怪死的不能再死,化灰飞了。解除血契后,“潇潇!嫁给我好不好?”“……好。”“你要吃什么我就……诶,你说啥?”“好!”鼓掌撒花祝贺白大少勾搭墨神子成功!
  • 职场文化:狼道VS羊道

    职场文化:狼道VS羊道

    每一个企业都有自己独特的风格,不同的环境造就不同的职场文化:欧美企业重视个性,所以轻松的人性化管理细节随处可见;日韩企业等级制度分明,人人要学会谦逊礼貌。而中国的职场文化又如何?一直以来,在激烈的市场竞争中,很多企业将“狼文化”作为自己的标杆,可是在“员工不堪压力而自杀”的事件不断曝光后,曾经风靡一时的“狼文化”受到质疑,职场人士开始倡导比较温和的“羊文化”。《职场文化:狼道VS羊道》全面分析“狼文化”和“羊文化”的特点,从中提取当今企业管理运营中的优势理念,把两者结合,双管齐下,帮助企业塑造合理、新颖、有效、有活力的企业文化。
  • 神封星穹

    神封星穹

    浩瀚宇宙,星空无垠。无尽的黑暗,似没有尽头,遥远的光,那是希望,还是黑暗的始端。深藏的传说,失落的世界,又在何方?……种族万千,姿态琼奇,黑与白的交汇,是全新的天地,还是又一片星空……在宇宙的一角,一颗枯寂昏黄的星球上,有一颗沉睡了千年的灵魂,在某一天,悄然的睁开了眼……
  • 陆离街之白川纵诡

    陆离街之白川纵诡

    夕阳西下。人声渐稀,街道慢慢安静了下来,各家店铺都准备关门,而在城东头那条街上,白日大门紧闭的店铺则纷纷开张,门外挂出流光溢彩的灯笼。每当这个时候,这条白日名为麓丽街的街道在传闻中有了第二个名字——陆离街。一条只在夜晚开张和热闹的街道,一条在传闻中鬼魅频出,诡异光怪,离奇事件层出不穷的街道。街口转角,衣衫褴褛满面灰尘的小姑娘飞快地跑着,眼见身后两个凶神恶煞的男人就要追上了她。她慌忙一扭身躲到了路边正准备收摊的卖萝卜小贩身旁半人高的大箩筐后面,蜷缩着瑟瑟发抖。
  • Dora Thorne

    Dora Thorne

    本书为公版书,为不受著作权法限制的作家、艺术家及其它人士发布的作品,供广大读者阅读交流。汇聚授权电子版权。